Ethical Aspects of Anesthesia Care





Key Points





  • Deontologic (“rules-based”) ethical theory and utilitarian (outcome-based) theory clash in clinical scenarios in which the interests of individual patients are pitted against the interests of larger populations.



  • In the United States, the predominant medical ethical principle is that of respect for the patient’s autonomy, and its expression is in the informed consent of patients for medical therapy.



  • Competent and autonomous individuals can make affirmative choices about their medical care and refuse any medical treatments, including lifesaving care. Competence is both functional and relative. Four elements of competent decision making are understanding, appreciation, reasoning, and evidence of a choice.



  • Minor patients have varying degrees of decision-making capacity, and they may have legal rights to make certain decisions. Pediatric patients should be involved to the degree that they can be in medical decision making, particularly regarding elective therapy.



  • Medical testing should follow the ethical principles of beneficence and nonmaleficence and should be based on clinically validated algorithms whenever possible. Medical tests with special social significance, such as pregnancy and human immunodeficiency virus testing, should be undertaken only with the patient’s informed consent and should not be undertaken without sound evidence that they are necessary and beneficial.



  • In general, the rights of pregnant women are weighed against the rights of fetuses in a decremental fashion as the fetus approaches and surpasses viable age. Laboring women are able to give informed consent, and the validity of “Ulysses directives” at the time of labor is ethically arguable.



  • Use of restraints is antithetical to promotion of autonomy, and anesthesiologists have both ethical and legal obligations to determine whether such extreme intervention is warranted. Coercing or using physical or chemical means to force competent patients to undergo treatment they are refusing is both unethical and illegal.



  • Respect for patients’ autonomy requires that we disclose mistakes to release patients from misconceptions about their medical past and enhance their ability to share decision making about their medical care.



  • An advance directive is a document executed by the patient before incapacity to provide the patient’s physicians with guidance in medical decision making when the patient cannot communicate for himself or herself: these directives include, but are not limited to, durable powers of attorney, living wills, transfusion decisions, do-not-attempt-resuscitation (DNAR) directives, and decisions regarding organ donation.



  • Surrogate decision makers explicitly act in “substituted judgment” to provide what the patient would have wanted and are not being asked merely for their own preferences. Surrogate decision makers at best only approximate the patient’s decisions.



  • Patients have moral and legal rights to refuse even life-sustaining therapy, including in the operating room. DNAR orders should not be automatically suspended for anesthesia and/or surgery, but rather require reconsideration of risks and benefits; the goals and decisions of competent patients should generally be honored.



  • Terminal care requires special knowledge and experience on the part of the physician. It requires expertise in medically supportive therapy, management of problematic symptoms, knowledge about physiologic changes in the dying patient, support and counseling of patients and families, understanding and respect for the patient’s autonomy and religious and cultural practices and beliefs, the ability to work within complex healthcare teams, the ability to communicate well, and empathy.



  • Several interventions have special ethical implications—fluid and nutritional management; the administration of sedatives and/or narcotics that have the potential to hasten death; the institution of deep continuous sedation; the administration of neuromuscular blocking agents; and deactivating pacemakers, ventricular assist devices, and implanted cardioverter-defibrillators.



  • Physician-assisted suicide (PAS) is the provision of medication and/or prescriptions to patients at their request for the purpose of ending their life. Euthanasia is the administration of medication by someone other than the patient for the express purpose of causing death. PAS and euthanasia are legal only in specific parts of the world, but they are strongly supported by the public.



  • Brain death is legally and medically defined as the point at which all cardiorespiratory function irreversibly ceases or all function of the whole brain irreversibly stops.



  • In donation after cardiac death (DCD), withdrawal of life support occurs with provisions for immediate organ donation after cardiac arrest. Controversies around DCD include concerns about when cardiopulmonary death can be declared and whether medications that preserve organ function but may hasten the donor’s death can be administered.



  • Research in human subjects must balance many conflicting interests such as the needs and rights of the research subject; the hypothetic interests of future patients; and the physician’s financial, professional, and personal goals. The ethical conduct of research in human subjects follows three principles: (1) respect for autonomy, and the obligation to protect subjects with limited autonomy; (2) beneficence, with obligations to minimize risks, maximize benefits, and ensure that the research design is scientifically sound; and (3) justice, the obligation to treat each person with regard to what is morally right and to ensure fair distribution of benefits and burdens.



  • Advances in understanding animal cognition have led most biologists to believe that many, if not all, animals are capable of feeling pleasure, pain, anticipation, and fear, and thus they experience both enjoyment and suffering. Allowing animal suffering because of pain, fear, sickness, or poor standards of care is a moral harm that must be avoided, mitigated, and weighed heavily against the benefits it produces.



  • U.S. professional organizations for physicians have consistently stated that participation in executions by physicians is unethical, and the American Board of Anesthesiologists states that participation in executions would constitute unprofessional behavior that would result in investigation and possible decertification of anesthesiologists.



  • “Conscientious objection” by physician to providing legally allowable medical care that violates their personal moral values is possible, but is limited and counterbalanced by a physician’s professional obligations to put the patient’s interests first.



Medicine is a respected profession with codes of behavior and definite rules of conduct. Modern medical practitioners have tremendous power, recognized social import, and powerful financial interactions that touch nearly everyone’s lives. The American Society of Anesthesiologists (ASA) has established principles for the ethical management of patients. This chapter examines the ethical bases of the practices of medicine and the implications for anesthesiologists.




Ethical Theory


Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Duty-Driven Ethics


The classic “paternalism” of medical practice was derived from virtue-based ethics. In this view, the physician is a genuinely virtuous person with inherent qualities of competence, sincerity, confidentiality, and altruism, who naturally knows and does what is correct for the patient. The patient, uneducated about medicine, has to trust the physician to decide what is best. Western society and legal systems have changed substantially since paternalism flourished, giving way to practices based in the four “pillars” of medical ethics: respect for patient autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence, and justice. Many different ethical frameworks are applied in modern medicine, but two of the most prominent frameworks relevant to western medicine are utilitarian ethics and deontology.


In utilitarian ethics , actions are judged right or wrong on the balance of their good and bad consequences. A “right” action produces the most good, based on a perspective that gives equal weight to the interests of all affected parties. Utilitarian theory is compelling but falls short in defining which benefits are most important. Is it the “good” that all reasonable people want or the “good” defined by the individual patient? What if the only way to maximize good is to commit an entirely immoral act? For example, what if the only way to win a war is to systematically torture children? Outcomes of actions continue to accumulate over time—when on that continuum is it appropriate to determine that an action was right or wrong? The “good” act of saving an individual’s life today may be viewed through a completely different lens when, 20 years from now, that same individual is revealed as a mass murderer.


Utilitarian theory may be best when applied to analyzing broad-based policies, in decisions regarding rationing of resources, and when attempting to resolve conflicting ethical obligations between several equally interested parties.


The premise of Kantian-based ethics (also called deontologic—or duty-based —theory) is that features of actions other than their consequences make them right or wrong. Intention is more important than outcome. Furthermore, no person should use another exclusively as a means to an end, because each person is the end for which we should act. No person should be used to further the purposes of another person without that other person’s autonomous consent. Kantian philosophy would forbid killing one innocent person to save another innocent person, for example.


Individualism and autonomy are valued highly in Western society, and people tend to turn to Kantian philosophy when ethical questions arise that balance the authority of the physician against the goals and values of individual patients.


Some of the toughest ethical questions in medical practice occur when the rights and desires of individual patients conflict with social policies. Clashes between deontologic and utilitarian principles are common in the intensive care unit (ICU), in managed care settings, in end-of-life care, in transplant medicine, in triage during civilian mass casualty events, and in the care of poor and older patients whose medical management is funded by the government. In each of these settings, the will of the individual patient may conflict with broader principles of minimizing expense, fairly allocating scarce resources, protecting the broader interests of many patients, and determining where and how society’s healthcare dollars are best spent.


The political tradition of the United States provides a clear underpinning to individual freedom, and at the beginning of the 20th century, the concept of the autonomy of patients began to emerge.




Clinical Ethics


Informed Consent and Informed Refusal


Legal and moral imperatives for informed consent are based on the ethical principle of respect for patient autonomy. Autonomy refers to the ability to choose without controlling interferences by others and without personal limitations that prevent meaningful choices, such as inadequate information or understanding. Individuals have the right to determine what happens to them to the degree to which they are capable. In the United States, this right is rooted in constitutional guarantees of privacy and noninterference. In 1914, the case of Schloendorff v Society of New York Hospital established that it was the right of “every human being of adult years and sound mind to determine what shall happen to his own body.” In 1957, the term informed consent was first used in the case of Salgo v Trustees of Leland Stanford Hospital , which established that it is not sufficient for physicians simply to secure consent; physicians have a duty to inform patients about the risks and alternatives to treatment, in addition to the procedures themselves and their consequences.


Respect for the patient’s autonomy requires physicians to respect decisions made by competent patients, but also to promote autonomy by removing barriers to competent participation in decisions. Such obstacles range from incomplete or inaccurate information to reversible medical conditions that impair a patient’s ability to understand the information given to him or her.


Competence and Capacity


Autonomy to make medical decisions cannot exist in the absence of competence. In the United States, competence is a legal determination, and capacity describes the necessary skills to participate in medical decisions. Most often, the terms are used interchangeably.


Impairments of capacity can be temporary or permanent. Examples include some mental illnesses, dementia, immaturity, anxiety, and pain. Medication effects can variously impede competence, or improve it, depending on their effects and the context in which they are given. Older patients, patients suffering from mental impairment, and children are particularly vulnerable to having their participation in medical decisions inappropriately curtailed or denied because their capacity to participate is frequently underestimated. Hearing loss, expressive aphasia, and other neurologic impairments can create the false impression that capacity is impaired. Many minors have the ability to make medical decisions but may be mistakenly excluded from the decision-making process solely because of their age. Language barriers can present significant challenges to communication.


Capacity is both relative and task specific. Patients may be able to understand and make decisions about medical issues while being unable to manage their financial affairs, for example.


Prejudice and paternalism permeate physician behavior in the informed consent process. Challenges to a patient’s competence frequently occur because the patient and the physician have a difference of opinion or values, and the majority of referred patients are found competent. Unwarranted challenges of a patient’s capacity may, intentionally or not, serve to allow the physician to dismiss, rather than solve, a dilemma regarding a difficult patient’s wishes, since with a finding of incapacity, the physician’s paternalism cannot then be trumped by patient autonomy. In a retrospective study, Katz and associates commented that referrals for urgent or serious treatment put pressure on a consulting psychiatrist to support the medical team’s wishes for intervention by simply declaring the patient incompetent. Treatment refusal may simply reflect a patient’s prioritization of other things (e.g., dignity, privacy, independence) other than medical outcomes, and not a problem with capacity—or it might reflect manageable emotions and values that disproportionately affect a patient’s choices, but do not necessarily rule out capacity.


Doctors are mistaken about patients’ preferences regarding life-extending therapies and underestimate older patients’ desires for life-extending therapies in 30% to 40% of cases. Moreover, surveys indicate that physicians and other healthcare workers are likely to act on their personal prejudices regarding handicapped or impaired patients.


Functional capacity for decision making must be judged separately from the perceived quality of the decision itself. Patients have the right to make “bad” decisions (i.e., decisions that the physician feels are less than optimal) if they are competent and have appropriate information. Otherwise, the physician would merely prevail whenever a disagreement occurred, and patient autonomy in medical decision making would be nonexistent.


How do we recognize competence? Competence is defined functionally , and it is task specific . It cannot be defined to be absent by the mere presence of specific diagnoses or medications. Furthermore, evidence of impairment is not sufficient to prove incompetency . With such high value placed in the United States on autonomy and self-determination, incompetency is, and should be, a difficult bar to leap over, requiring that only persons with impairments “that place them at the very bottom of the performance curve” should be declared incompetent. A “sliding scale” approach to competence determinations, rather than an all-or-none approach, is endorsed by the President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, and generally reflects how courts deal with competency cases.


Anesthesiologists frequently ask whether valid consent can be obtained after the patient has received premedication. Claims that premedications automatically invalidate consent demonstrate a lack of understanding of the concept of competence. If it were true that benzodiazepines and narcotics, for example, automatically invalidate consent, then we would have to consider the consent of almost all chronic pain patients invalid. In one study, 37.5% of geriatric patients presented for surgery having taken self-prescribed medications and over 25% of these were analgesics and benzodiazepines. If competence were automatically invalidated by the presence of specific medications, then we would be forced to carry out drug testing on all preoperative patients before obtaining consent. While it is true that sometimes premedication can interfere with a patient’s ability to give consent, in some circumstances, patients cannot give consent without premedication. A patient who is in severe pain, for example, is unlikely to be able to focus on detailed risks and alternatives of a proposed procedure without first receiving medication. In that case, treatment of severe pain may actually improve competence during the informed consent process.


How does the anesthesiologist determine if they are dealing with a competent patient? Multiple reviews by competency consultants agree that there are several functional elements to competence: (1) Understanding – Can the patient receive and understand treatment-related information? (2) Appreciation – Does the patient have insight about the disorder and its consequences and potential treatment options? Does the patient understand that treatment could be beneficial in some way? (3) Reasoning – Is the patient able to use logic to compare the risks and benefits of treatment alternatives? And, (4) Evidence of a choice – Can the patient communicate a choice?


In respecting and promoting patient autonomy in medical decision making, the anesthesiologist has an ethical duty to treat reversible conditions that interfere with medical decision making when doing so would not delay the medical treatment so much that it becomes irrelevant. Elective surgery may have to be postponed until expert consultation for a determination of mental capacity or treatment of reversible conditions can occur. When surgery in an impaired patient is urgent, the anesthesiologist may have to rely on a surrogate decision maker or proceed with the best determination of the patient’s interests in mind. It is important to note that the mere presence of an emergency does not invalidate a competent patient’s rights to consent to or to refuse treatment. Overriding a competent patient’s wishes is unethical, even in emergency situations.


Disclosure


The informed consent process requires honest disclosure of medical information to the patient. U.S. courts generally rely on two standards of disclosure, termed the reasonable person (or objective person) standard and the subjective standard. In the reasonable person standard , the physician must disclose any information that a theoretically reasonable person would want to know, and the risks or cluster of risks to which a reasonable person in the patient’s position would attach significance in deciding whether or not to forgo the proposed therapy. This standard does not require an exhaustive recitation of facts, and it acknowledges that not all information related to the procedure is integral to making a decision about whether to undergo that procedure. The subjective standard recognizes that some patients may have special needs for specific information, and when that need is obvious or has been brought to the attention of the physician, the information must be disclosed. A concert violinist may have a specific need to know about the potential for nerve damage from an axillary block, while an opera singer may need to know that intubation may adversely affect the voice. In obtaining informed consent, the anesthesiologist should always ask the patient if there are any special concerns regarding the anesthetic, or anything he or she would want the provider to know. In general, legal and ethical standards now require that the physician (1) accurately discuss the therapy and its potential alternative—including no therapy—and (2) disclose the common risks, because they are more likely to happen, and the serious risks, because the consequences are severe.


The doctrine of therapeutic privilege is sometimes cited to avoid discussing risks, the reasoning being that discussing risks can psychologically or physically harm the patient by increasing stress. Studies of patients’ stress during the informed consent process do not support this concept. These studies show that patient stress is generally reduced after risk discussions and omission of such conversations is contrary to U.S. law. Although it is ethical to forgo or curtail risk discussions at the patient’s request, it is not ethical for the physician to decide to do so unilaterally.


The physician-patient relationship is inherently unequal because of the physician’s knowledge and authority and the patient’s dependence on the physician for care. Physicians have ethical obligations to avoid exploiting their influence for the purpose of accomplishing their own ends. Although offering a rational basis for a medical choice is acceptable, it is always unethical to coerce or manipulate competent patients into decisions by presenting real or implied threats or by omitting or misrepresenting key information. In fact, such intentional manipulations are morally equivalent to lying to the patient, and thus invalidate the concept of informed consent entirely.


Legal Implications of Informed Consent


The informed consent process does not prevent legal liability when adverse events occur. Flawed informed consent processes have been cited, however, as evidence of a lack of quality of care by the physician, and are associated with poorer litigation outcomes for the physician. The ASA closed-claims database reveals that informed consent is cited in approximately 1% of cases, and cases with inadequate informed consent documentation are associated with larger monetary awards. Studies show that the risk of a malpractice claim is directly related to the patient’s perception of his or her relationship with the physician. The informed consent process provides one of the few opportunities anesthesiologists have to establish that relationship, however brief, and the medicolegal importance of that process should not be underestimated.


Informed Refusal


The concept of informed consent is moot if the informed patient cannot refuse medical therapy, because every informed consent process would then have to end with the physician getting his or her way. Examples of informed refusals in anesthesiology include requests to withdraw or withhold life-supporting care in the ICU; do-not-attempt-resuscitation (DNAR) orders in the operating room; refusals of blood transfusions; and cases in which a patient refuses preoperative testing, such as human immunodeficiency virus (HIV) or pregnancy testing.


Informed refusal has concerns and requirements similar to those of informed consent. When patients refuse medical care or insist on what the physician believes to be suboptimal care, disclosure of the risks and benefits becomes even more important because these decisions may veer from options that are already widely accepted and for which the risks are believed to be lowest. It is easier to justify agreeing to the unusual preferences of a well-informed patient than to justify subjecting a poorly informed patient to unorthodox care.


Despite full information, patients may sometimes request or demand care that is unreasonable, either because it will adversely affect the performance of a surgical procedure or because it would be associated with unreasonably high risks. When a patient demands a technique that is inappropriate or outside of the realm of reasonable practice, the anesthesiologist is under no ethical obligation to provide that care. No physician can be compelled by a patient to practice negligently.




Special Issues in Informed Consent and Informed Refusal


The Jehovah s Witness Patient


The classic example of a patient who refuses therapy in anesthesia practice is that of Jehovah’s Witnesses, many of whom believe that accepting a blood transfusion violates a Biblical injunction. The Jehovah’s Witness doctrine has been subject to change over time, with resulting inconsistencies in religious practice regarding which, if any, blood components may be acceptable. Individuals interpret religious doctrines in light of their own spiritual contexts, and not all believers hold to the same tenets with identical fervor. Church doctrines, like medical practices, evolve over time, and practices that are acceptable at one time may not be years later. Anesthesiologists and surgeons have cited individual and doctrinal inconsistencies as justification for ignoring the wishes of Jehovah’s Witness patients, but to do so is no more logical than assuming that every hypertensive patient needs or will respond well to identical treatment or that optimal treatments will not evolve over time. Moreover, any patient has the right to refuse blood transfusion therapy, regardless of whether this desire is founded in religious preference. Such refusals have become more common in patients who are not Jehovah’s Witnesses, as blood transfusion therapy has been connected to infection risk and other complications.


Because of the differing beliefs of Jehovah’s Witness patients, the anesthesiologist must have a thorough and detailed preoperative discussion of possible therapies with the patient, and the conclusions should be documented in the patient’s chart. A physician who cannot comply with a competent adult patient’s desire to forgo transfusion has an ethical obligation to find an alternative caregiver whenever possible.


The courts strongly support the rights of most adult patients to refuse blood products for themselves but have been inconsistent and have interfered in cases of some pregnant patients. Transfusion of pediatric Jehovah’s Witness patients by court order is common. However, this may become ethically and legally less acceptable as alternative bloodless therapies to maintain oxygen-carrying capacity evolve, as the Jehovah’s Witness church further defines its doctrines with regard to children, and as the capacity of children to consent to or refuse therapy is better understood.


The Pediatric Patient and Other Patients With Impaired Competence


The ethical practice of medicine weighs heavily toward adherence to the respect for autonomy of competent patients or advance directives of patients who were previously competent. Medical care of individuals who have never been autonomous relies on principles such as respect for human dignity, beneficence, avoidance of harm, and adherence to the principle of justice.


Children are examples of persons who may or may not yet be autonomous. Laws in each state define the age at which children become legally competent to make medical decisions (usually 18 years), but many younger children have the mental and emotional capacity to make medical decisions. Forcing such individuals to undergo treatments they do not want is unethical and could be illegal as well.


Decision-making capacity in children is variable. Most 2-year-old children are clearly not able to make medical decisions. However, the range of capability in children as young as 7 or 8 years old is wide. In one study, children 6 through 9 years of age who were invited to participate in influenza vaccine research asked pertinent questions about individual risks and benefits and whether their community and other children would benefit. Studies suggest that the average 12-year-old adolescent has capabilities that are required in medical decision-making, but differing influences of the brain’s well-developed reward system coupled with underdevelopment of the brain’s control systems suggest that decision-making capacity may in fact be diminished in specific contexts in this age group.


Most states recognize “emancipated minor” status, in which a court determines that a minor can legally make medical decisions for himself or herself. Legal exceptions to the age of consent are recognized in most states when treatment is believed to be in the minor’s best interest and when a requirement for parental consent would interfere with the child’s ability to receive medical help. The law recognizes that, tragically, some conditions for which a minor seeks therapy may even be the result of parental abuse and seeking parental permission for treatment may actually further endanger the minor. One quarter of pregnant teens are at risk for physical or sexual assault, and the most common perpetrator is a member of their family. Thus, minors are allowed in many states to consent for treatment for substance abuse, sexually transmitted disease, mental illness, and medical care affecting pregnancy, including abortion, without seeking parental consent. When a minor has decision-making capacity but is not “emancipated,” a judge may declare the child to be a “mature minor” with decision-making rights.


Ideally, individuals of any age should be involved in medical decisions to the degree that their capacity allows. Children ages 7 to 17 have been shown to desire comprehensive perioperative information, including details of the procedure and anesthesia, risks, and complications. A minor with capacity to make decisions should not be coerced or restrained under most circumstances. Determining whether a minor has such capacity may require formal consultation and assessment. The American Academy of Pediatrics has stated that physicians who care for children “should give serious consideration to each patient’s developing capacities for participating in decision making, including rationality and autonomy.” The term assent rather than consent is used to refer to agreement to treatment from children who do not fall into legal categories, such as age, that award adult rights. Recently, authors have suggested that informed consent rather than assent for medical research participation should be applied to children ages 12 and up.


When children dissent from medical care, persistent refusals may be ethically binding, particularly in the case of participation in research. Medical personnel should respect the wishes of a patient who withholds assent and should try to gain a better understanding of the patient’s situation or deal with his or her fears. “A patient’s reluctance or refusal to assent should also carry considerable weight when the proposed intervention is not essential to his or her welfare and/or can be deferred without substantial risk.”


Ethical Challenges of Preoperative Testing


The ethical implications of genetic testing have been widely discussed in the literature, but the ethical implications of routine medical testing have been largely overlooked by professional societies. The performance of diagnostic tests does have ethical dimensions, however. We generally undertake such tests precisely because we intend to help the patient (beneficence) or to use the information to minimize other risks (nonmaleficence). Certain medical tests may also carry implications for the patient’s autonomy, privacy, and even social justice.


Routine Preoperative Testing Protocols


Preoperative testing may help identify unrecognized or disguised conditions that could adversely affect anesthetic risk. All medical tests carry risks, however. False-positive and false-negative results may either label patients as having a condition they do not have or inappropriately assure patients that they do not have a condition that they do. Erroneous results may lead either to further testing or to inappropriate and unnecessary therapy associated with further complications. Errors can also cause patients to be deprived of important therapy they would otherwise receive. Tests sometimes have accompanying physical complications, and they are certainly always associated with economic costs. Systematic over-testing increases the costs of health care for entire populations, unnecessarily burdening an already costly system, and diverting badly needed funds to unnecessary enterprise. Medical tests may involve problems of conflicts of interest if the ordering physician has an economic relationship with the entity that carries out the tests. Additionally, not all medical tests are ethically equivalent. Certain tests, such as pregnancy testing and HIV testing, may have complex social consequences and can lead to serious, avoidable harms.


Modern medicine is a science that incorporates theories that are expected to be consistent and generalizable. Although all data are deeply theory laden, the practice of evidence-based medicine (EBM) is founded on the concept that conscientious, judicious, and explicit use of the best available medical evidence should be integrated with clinical experience derived from systematic research in making decisions about the medical care of individual patients. In general, nonsystematic clinical experience, anecdote, and untested theory are not sufficient grounds for clinical decision making.


EBM and medical ethics share common principles and goals: both are aimed at maximizing benefits and minimizing risks, as well as at involving the patient in shared decision making. Using EBM to guide clinical testing and therapy is supported by analysis of traditional therapies that were never subjected to rigorous testing and that, on examination, were shown to be not only unhelpful to patients but possibly harmful. One Cochrane review, for example, found that administration of human albumin, a mainstay of therapy for treatment of shock, may be associated with increased mortality. Another Cochrane review demonstrated that although mammography screening will prolong the life of 1 in 2000 women over a 10-year period, it will lead to the false diagnosis of cancer and the institution of cancer treatment in 10 women during that same period; these findings raise serious questions about the benefits and risks of routine mammography. Using systematic evaluation of medical diagnostic testing to develop principles of preoperative testing not only serves the ethical principles of beneficence and nonmaleficence, but also permits us to provide patients with accurate and up-to-date information on the potential benefits of tests to aid their understanding and input in their medical care—thus honoring the principle of respect for the patient’s autonomy.


Conversely, EBM presents potentially significant ethical concerns. In relying on traditional medical experimentation, EBM may not sufficiently account for the role of social and cultural factors (e.g., poverty, ethnicity, spirituality, and gender) in health, and instead may rely too heavily on a narrowly drawn biomedical model of the patient’s experience of health and disease. In the words of Rogers, “those with the greatest burden of ill health are disenfranchised, as there is little research that is relevant to them, there is poor access to treatments, and attention is diverted from activities that might have a much greater impact on their health.”


Despite its limitations, it nevertheless seems reasonable to believe that in trying to maximize beneficence and minimize nonmaleficence, EBM provides at least an improvement in the search for a rational, cost-effective approach to medical testing over simply adopting “traditional” therapies or protocols without evidence that they will contribute to accomplishing those goals. Applying medical tests inappropriately can cause very real harm to patients. Simply stated, if medical care is not valid, then it is not ethical.


Evidence that routine tests or traditional patterns of preoperative testing enhance perioperative outcomes is scant. Large population studies of many routine preoperative tests, such as coagulation screening, chest radiography, and electrocardiography, have, on the contrary, found that these tests increase costs without necessarily positively affecting outcomes and can even lead to detrimental outcomes. The ASA Task Force for Preanesthesia Evaluation acknowledged that most routine testing is not necessary. When evidence-based algorithms for preoperative testing are available and have been appropriately validated clinically, they should be used to guide clinical decision making.


Routine Preoperative Pregnancy and Human Immunodeficiency Virus Testing


Social risks of preoperative testing may not be as obvious to the physician as medical risks, but they can be the source of significant harm. Examples of tests that can produce social harm and are of limited preoperative utility are HIV and pregnancy tests. Both tests have serious ethical consideration; have limited, if any, beneficial impact in the setting of surgery; may have serious social and economic consequences for the patient beyond the operating room; and require the patient’s informed consent.


HIV tests are often ordered for the purpose of singling out patients for whom extra universal precautions could be taken to reduce transmission in the operating room. Most surgeons and anesthesiologists believe that compulsory HIV testing would reduce their risk of exposure, and many believe incorrectly that this testing is the physician’s prerogative and can be done without the patient’s consent.


However, HIV testing does not necessarily yield safer anesthetic management and is more costly than diligent application of universal precautions. In low-prevalence populations, testing is more likely to give false-negative results that wrongly reassure operating room workers that a patient is not infected. This may paradoxically increase the risk of HIV transmission if relaxation in vigilance is the result.


HIV tests can result in loss of employment, insurance coverage, or both. Seropositive women can experience marital breakup, abandonment, verbal abuse, and physical violence if their status is disclosed. The threat of compulsory HIV testing almost certainly would prevent some patients from seeking needed surgical care.


Routine preoperative pregnancy testing has ethical ramifications analogous to those of HIV testing. Despite pervasive beliefs to the contrary, studies do not conclusively demonstrate that anesthetic agents lead to early fetal loss, and no anesthetics have been clearly associated with teratogenic effects. Studies have also shown that even adolescent girls generally accurately report the possibility of pregnancy when asked privately. Legal ramifications of not routinely testing for pregnancy preoperatively have been virtually nonexistent, and fewer than one third of practices in the United States require such testing. A positive pregnancy test may have extremely negative consequences if a vulnerable patient is in a social situation in which pregnancy is not accepted. Up to two-thirds of sexual assault victims are minors, and some are the result of child rape within the home. Abandonment, negative family interactions, and violence to the patient or her fetus, or both, may all occur, as reactions to revelation of the pregnancy, attempts to hide a sexual domestic crime, or even in some cases as “honor killings.” Referral of pregnant adolescents to child protective services should be considered. In many states, it is illegal to disclose or even insinuate a child’s pregnancy status to her parents, regardless of her age. Therefore, the anesthesiologist who discovers an adolescent patient’s pregnancy has few comfortable or legal options.


Many patients may choose not to undergo an elective surgical procedure if they know they are pregnant. However, coercing a female patient to have a test against her wishes and that she may find insulting explicitly violates the principle of the patient’s autonomy. The physician’s self-interest is not adequate justification for disregarding a patient’s autonomy or violating a patient’s privacy. The ASA Task Force on Preoperative Testing and the ASA Committee on Ethics jointly recommended that anesthesiologists offer the choice of preoperative pregnancy testing to any female patient who may desire it, explain the potential risks and benefits, and obtain informed consent or informed refusal for the test.




Ethics of Anesthesia Involving Pregnant Women


Maternal-Fetal Conflicts


In general, the rights of pregnant women to refuse therapy, even if it will be detrimental to their fetuses, are protected under right-to-privacy provisions in the U.S. Constitution. Those rights are weighed against potential harms to the fetus in a decremental fashion as the fetus approaches and surpasses viable age. When the fetus is of nonviable age, the mother’s rights prevail. Court decisions have consistently upheld the rights of pregnant women to have abortions, to not be subjected to drug testing, and to forgo transfusions early in pregnancy. Attempts to charge women with child abuse, child endangerment, drug trafficking, murder, and attempted murder for activities deemed dangerous to their fetuses have almost uniformly failed. In general, women do not lose their rights to bodily integrity and informed consent when they become pregnant, and neither fetal “rights” nor state interests supersede a pregnant woman’s right as medical decision maker.


The American Academy of Pediatrics Committee on Ethics outlined conditions that in their view are necessary to override a mother’s refusal of care: (1) the fetus will suffer irrevocable harm without the treatment, (2) the treatment is clearly indicated and likely to be effective, and (3) the risk to the woman is low. The American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists condemned the use of coercion in pregnant women and advocated counseling the patient carefully about risks, as well as consultation with an ethics committee.


Informed Consent in Laboring Women


The validity of informed consent for epidural anesthesia in laboring women is a topic of concern to anesthesiologists, who periodically raise the question whether laboring women are able to consider and weigh the risks of labor analgesia sufficiently while they are in pain. Although ideal conditions for informed consent are often lacking during labor, it is important to realize that the ideal is seldom achieved even in elective surgical patients; therefore, it is crucial to distinguish between conditions that are not ideal from conditions that are not adequate .


Despite concerns by anesthesiologists, most studies show that laboring women have the same capacity to give informed consent as the general surgical population, are able to recall details of the consent process long after labor is finished, and indicate that labor did not alter their decision making. Furthermore, studies show that the presence or absence of labor pain has minimal effect on a woman’s ability to recall analgesia risks and other elements of the informed consent process later. Some investigators argue that it is only after the patient enters active labor and she can assess for herself the severity of pain and consequences of proceeding without analgesia that she can be fully informed.


An ethical conflict can arise in the case of so-called Ulysses directives in which, before labor, a woman executes an advance directive that refuses epidural analgesia and instructs doctors to ignore her pleas for epidural anesthesia at the time of labor should she change her mind. Although some experts suggest that ignoring the Ulysses directive disrespects a woman’s long-term preferences, others argue that “information and valid experience are critical prerequisites for autonomous decision making” and that only the current wish (to receive an epidural) is ethically relevant. Such cases appear to have no clear and unequivocal ethical ground on which to proceed, and circumstances must guide the physician. However, if an anesthesia practice decides to disregard Ulysses directives routinely, this should obviously be disclosed to patients in advance of labor whenever possible.




The Uncooperative Patient Coercion and Restraint


The use of physical restraint to control medical research subjects was first directly addressed in the Nuremberg Code following the Doctors’ Trial in 1947 to 1949 and is a continuing subject of intense scrutiny. For anesthesiologists, chemical restraints often replace physical ones, but the ethical issues are the same. Anesthesiologists are often asked by medical colleagues to chemically restrain uncooperative patients. Use of restraints is antithetical to promotion of autonomy, and anesthesiologists have both ethical and legal obligations to determine whether such extreme intervention is warranted. Coercing or using physical or chemical means to force a competent patient to undergo treatment that he or she is refusing is both unethical and illegal. Refusal of medical care and angry behavior are not proof of incompetence, intoxication, or inability to make medical decisions.


When faced with the uncooperative adult patient, questions to ask include the following: (1) Is the patient clearly incompetent or merely angry and uncooperative? Does the patient show evidence of neurologic impairment, acute intoxication, or severe mental disability? (2) Is the patient in imminent danger? (3) Does the patient pose a direct threat to staff or other patients? (4) Does a compelling need to treat life-threatening injuries exist? In the absence of any of the foregoing, the use of coercion or physical or chemical restraints is neither ethical nor legal. Physicians may be forced in some situations to act within a time frame that does not permit lengthy evaluation of a patient’s competence or a protracted search for a surrogate decision maker. The standard applied in such cases would be to do what a “reasonable” person would wish. Coercion or restraint (or both) in such situations is not ideal, but it may be necessary and ethically permissible.


The uncooperative child presents special ethical concerns. When a patient who does not have the capacity to make healthcare decisions dissents from medical care, the anesthesiologist is ethically required to provide care that is most likely to benefit the patient and prevent harm while preserving the dignity and safety of the patient. Although violation of respect for autonomy is technically not possible in a patient who does not have autonomy, violations of principles of beneficence, nonmaleficence, and respect for dignity certainly are. Indiscriminate use of physical or chemical restraints is not without physical risk, and the fear and anger provoked by such tactics can lead to future aversion of medical care and mistrust of healthcare providers. The American Academy of Pediatrics Committee on Child Abuse and Neglect stated that restraint should not be used in pediatric care “unless it is necessary for proper diagnosis and treatment in a sick child, as in the case of a child with a high fever and potential ear infection, or in emergency situations.”


Behavioral control in the uncooperative child or incompetent adult should focus on alternatives to physical restraint, such as offering choices on how to go to sleep and use of fantasy or hypnotic suggestion. Despite many possible social, economic, and scheduling pressures to the contrary, delaying or rescheduling a surgical procedure in a hysterical patient is better than using coercion or force. Delaying elective surgery may reduce stress, allow adequate premedication, and promote safer induction conditions. If medical care is urgent, or if delay is unlikely to result in better conditions for the patient, then the anesthesiologist should proceed in a manner designed to preserve the patient’s dignity and safety.




Truth Telling Disclosure of Errors and Apology


Nonmaleficence has been a foundational principle for the medical profession since the time of Hippocrates, and this principle draws no distinction between deliberate and unintended harms. Medical care is fraught with uncertainty, risk, and error. Harms resulting from unexpected complications, accidents, systems issues, and medical mistakes are to be avoided with equal diligence whenever possible.


Wu and colleagues defined a medical mistake as “a commission or omission with potentially negative consequences for the patient that would have been judged wrong by skilled and knowledgeable peers at the time it occurred, independent of whether there are any negative consequences.” Medical errors occur in 3% to 5% of all hospitalizations. More than 40% appear to be preventable, and more than 15% result in patients’ deaths. In 1999, the release of the Institute of Medicine’s report To Err Is Human focused public and political attention on the terrible fallout of medical errors in the United States.


Studies showed that 76% of physicians admitted to a serious medical error that they did not disclose to the patient, and 22% of physicians indicated that they would not disclose an error that caused a patient’s death. Reasons cited for a physician’s reluctance to disclose errors included personal shame, fear of loss of prestige in the physician’s cohort, fear of direct reprisal, lack of experience in disclosing uncomfortable information, fear of causing further harm (emotional or psychological) to the patient and family, and fear of litigation. In many cases, legal advice to physicians has discouraged disclosure and apology in the erroneous belief that these tactics decrease medicolegal liability.


Obfuscating the root cause of a patient’s complication when it is caused by a medical error is not difficult in the physician-patient relationship because the physician has unique expertise and is the recipient of unique trust. Furthermore, a minimum standard of disclosure simply does not exist. The Code of Ethics of the American Medical Association (AMA) states that patients have a right to be free of misconceptions about their medical condition and that physicians have ethical obligations to “inform the patient of all the facts necessary to ensure understanding of what has occurred.” However, the AMA Code of Ethics addresses only “harms” and not “errors, thus implying no duty to disclose medical errors that do not lead to harm. Although some experts state that physicians may have a lesser obligation to disclose harmless errors and/or “near misses,” it is nevertheless arguable that they should consider doing so. The physician has little to lose, and such disclosures may enhance discussion of medical care with the patient and result in a strengthened doctor-patient relationship. Legalistically, some experts consider full disclosure of medical errors to be an extension of the legal principle underlying informed consent: “Clearly, if the patient is entitled to know the risks of a procedure and what could go wrong prior to giving their consent, it follows that they would be entitled to know if something has in fact gone wrong, regardless of whether it was unanticipated.”


Respect for patients’ autonomy requires that we disclose mistakes that harm patients because in so doing we release patients from misconceptions about their medical past and enhance their ability to share decision making about their medical care. Disclosure prevents mistaken attribution by the patient of adverse consequences to noncontributory causes. Disclosure is usually necessary for informed consent for treatments to address complications of the error. Disclosure may enhance patients’ trust in physicians. Moreover, disclosure may facilitate a patient’s obtaining just and fair compensation for economic consequences of the injury, such as lost work and pay.


The concern that disclosure of errors to patients will increase litigation or decrease patients’ trust, either in the doctor involved or in doctors in general, has not been borne out. Studies have suggested that full disclosure of a medical error reduces the likelihood that patients will change doctors, improves patients’ satisfaction, increases trust in the physician, and leads to a more positive emotional response. Studies also have demonstrated that patients take legal action because they want more honesty from their physicians and assurances that the physician has learned from the mistake and that future patients therefore are less likely to suffer.


An often-ignored aspect of medical errors is the effect that errors and disclosures have on physicians and other healthcare workers, who experience anxiety, fear, guilt, shame, self-doubt, anger, and disappointment. Damage to physicians, nurses, and others can be both long-lasting and severe, particularly following serious errors, manifesting as substance abuse and suicide. In a survey of anesthesiologists, 84% had been involved in at least one unanticipated death or serious injury, 88% stated they needed extended time to recover, with 19% stating they never fully recovered after the event. Twelve percent considered a career change. Even though 67% considered their ability to provide care was compromised in the first 4 hours following the event, only 7% were given time off. Five percent admitted to turning to drugs or alcohol as a coping mechanism. Most anesthesiologists report inadequate support from colleagues or their institution in coping with such events.


Physicians benefit from a sense of relief after disclosure and, at least in many cases, the forgiveness of the patient. Disclosure helps physicians learn and improve their practice. Failures to report errors, learn from errors, and communicate errors and their potential solutions within a healthcare system are major causes of medical errors themselves. One could argue that a physician who does not disclose a preventable error, such that it is repeated, bears responsibility for harm not only to his or her own patient, but also to all future patients in whom the error could have been prevented had it been disclosed.


Disclosure can present some harm to the physician: disclosure is stressful, litigation may result, malpractice premiums may increase, and future employment may be adversely affected. However, in the doctor-patient relationship, ethical frameworks hold that benefits and harms to the patient should hold more weight than benefits and harms to the physician.


Do we have an ethical duty to disclose the errors of others? Legally, some North American courts have held that we do not, and social norms about “tattling” on others are powerful deterrents to such disclosures. The reporting physician may hesitate because of a lack of definitive information, potential accusations of interfering in the doctor-patient relationship of another, worry that professional interactions such as patient referrals and performance evaluations may be affected, and fear of libel suits. When a physician observes a medical error committed by another physician, the options include nondisclosure, recommendations to the involved physician to disclose the error, disclosure of the error to a third party such as a risk-management group, or direct disclosure to the patient. Although no strict legal guidelines are in place, ethical principles favor actions that lead the patient to have a full understanding of what has occurred during his or her medical care.


Apology (as opposed to disclosure) remains a controversial aspect of communication following medical errors, largely because of fear that it could be used as an admission of negligence in subsequent litigation. Yet apology appears in many cases to decrease the risk of subsequent litigation, and lack of apology is a commonly cited reason among malpractice plaintiffs for their legal action. Spurred on by a desire to reduce litigation, many states have enacted “apology laws” that prohibit use of various types of apologies in court against physician defendants in malpractice cases. The impact of these laws and the impact of apologies on the incidence and outcomes of malpractice litigation remains unclear, although significant numbers of patients who have sued physicians indicate that an apology would have prevented them from doing so.


Advance Directives and Surrogate Decision Makers


Critical decisions regarding medical care often arise when patients are too ill to formulate or express decisions regarding medical interventions. Advance directives were developed after several legal decisions affirmed that patients can refuse even lifesaving medical care and that clear and convincing evidence of the patient’s wishes is needed to allow surrogate decision makers to request withdrawal of life-sustaining therapies. An advance directive is a document executed by the patient before incapacity to provide the patient’s physicians with guidance when the patient cannot communicate for himself or herself. Such directives include the following: living wills, which detail the therapies a patient would accept or refuse in the case of terminal incapacity; DNAR orders; and any other preferences regarding medical care decisions.


A surrogate decision maker is someone whom the patient has appointed to make healthcare decisions for him or her (a durable power of attorney [durable POA]) or an individual with other legally recognized authority by virtue of his or her relationship with the patient.


A durable POA for healthcare decisions may be given by the patient to a specific person he or she designates to make healthcare decisions for them if they become incapacitated. The authority vested in a POA supersedes most other decision makers, including family members, except a court-appointed guardian.


When the patient has not designated a durable POA, doctors rely on family members to make decisions for the patient. Many states have a legally defined hierarchy of decision makers. Commonly, the surrogate hierarchy is the spouse or legally recognized domestic partner, followed by the children, if all are in agreement, then parents, if both are in agreement, and then siblings, if all are in agreement. The anesthesiologist should familiarize himself or herself with the specific laws of the state in which they practice.


Surrogate decision makers are explicitly trusted to act in “substituted judgment” to provide what the patient would have wanted and theoretically are not asked merely for their own preferences. However, surrogate decision makers at best only approximate the patient’s decisions because their interpretation is subject to their own biases, values, and psychological agendas. Incompetent patients can be emotionally and financially burdensome, and decision makers may have conflicts of interest that distort their beliefs and testimony about what the patient would have wanted.


Studies demonstrate that patients and their proxies only infrequently discuss issues and values involving life-sustaining technologies. Discrepancies between patients and proxies are often significant in the assessment of patients’ emotional health and satisfaction. Neither physicians nor proxies can always accurately predict the patient’s preferences for life-sustaining therapies. Nevertheless, with all the imperfections, proxy decision making may be the only option if a patient has not left specific directives.


Medical Decisions That May Require a Court Order


Some medical treatments have intense cultural connotations, may involve limitation on private freedoms such as reproduction, or may have historically been subject to abuse. Decisions regarding these interventions cannot be made by a surrogate decision maker (even if one is available) and require a court review. Examples of such treatments in many states include sterilization and electroshock therapy.


The anesthesiologist should review the patient’s record before taking the patient to the operating room and ascertain (1) whether the patient has advance directives, (2) who the patient’s surrogate decision makers are, (3) whether the procedure is legally allowed with consent from a surrogate decision maker, and (4) in special cases, whether an appropriate court order has been obtained.


Do-Not-Attempt-Resuscitation Orders in the Operating Room


Up to 60% of anesthesiologists wrongfully believe that DNAR orders are automatically suspended during anesthesia and surgery. The ASA, the American College of Surgeons, the Association of Operating Room Nurses, and The Joint Commission all published practice guidelines requiring reconsideration, not abandonment, of the DNAR orders in the perioperative period.


The causes and outcomes expected with a cardiac arrest in the operating room are different from what may happen outside the operating room, although they are still poor, with a “viable” survival of only about 25%. It is important, therefore, that patients be informed of the risks and benefits of cardiac resuscitation so that they can best determine whether to ask for their DNAR order to be suspended during the perioperative period.


Although the patient’s primary care physician may have introduced the idea of DNAR orders to the patient or the surrogate decision maker, it is the anesthesiologist’s duty to discuss the risks and benefits of resuscitation in the setting of anesthesia and surgery before undertaking the patient’s care. The anesthesiologist should include in this discussion the following steps: (1) determine the patient’s goals regarding surgery and resuscitation; (2) establish exactly what is meant by “resuscitation,” in contrast to routine anesthetic care; (3) educate the patient about the risks and benefits of resuscitation in the operating room setting; and (4) document the agreements reached with the patient about which interventions commonly associated with resuscitation are acceptable to him or her. Such interventions could include, but are not limited to, intubation, administration of vasoactive drugs, administration of direct current countershock, and institution of chest compressions. Many patients who express reluctance about resuscitation during surgery actually most fear burdensome collateral outcomes, such as permanent neurologic impairment, rather than the process of resuscitation itself. Education and discussion may reassure these patients about the potential outcomes of resuscitation in the operating room and can establish ground rules for discontinuing interventions postoperatively if they do not lead to a chance of meaningful recovery.


Surgery depends on the cooperation of many caregivers with differing expertise, each with independent ethical obligations to the patient. Resuscitation agreements must be discussed with other members of the operating room team. This communication prevents crucial disagreements from occurring during a critical event when treatment decisions must be made quickly. It also allows “conscientious objectors” to withdraw from the healthcare team.


Advance directives are legally and ethically binding. Despite clear, consistent, and forceful legal decisions, physicians have ignored DNAR directives under the false assumption that the legal authority of advance directives and living wills is not binding in the operating room or that the physician has discretion in deciding when to follow or ignore such directives—and families have sued for significant monetary damages for the costs of continued health care and punitive damages for the pain, suffering, and mental anguish of the patients’ survivors when DNAR instructions are ignored.


In 1990, the U.S. Congress passed the Patient Self-Determination Act that recognizes a competent patient’s right to refuse any medical therapy, including life-sustaining therapy, and requires medical institutions and providers to advise patients of these rights and ask about their preferences. Compliance with the act is required in order to participate in Medicare and Medicaid reimbursements. Furthermore, in 2006, the American Civil Liberties Union filed suit against a group of New Mexico orthopedic surgeons who were requiring patients to sign away their rights to DNAR as a requirement of surgery, arguing that this not only violated the 1990 Patient Self-Determination Act, but denied patients their constitutional rights. The surgeons were required to desist in that practice, publicize the change in policy (to respect DNAR), and pay attorneys’ fees and various other fines.


Finally, DNAR orders must never be construed as an excuse to not “care” for the patient. A patient’s decision to forgo resuscitation does not imply a wish to avoid other beneficial interventions. Placement of a pulmonary artery catheter, for example, may help ensure optimal management of a frail patient who has a DNAR order and enable the anesthesiologist to avoid situations in which the patient’s DNAR status becomes pivotal.


End-of-Life Decision Making


A 1996 review by the AMA showed that the following end-of-life issues were of foremost importance to patients: control over the timing and location of death; management of symptoms such as pain, dyspnea, anxiety, and depression; financial management of medical care; and maintenance of therapeutic options, including physician-assisted suicide (PAS).


Withdrawal or Withholding of Medical Therapies


Between 2000 and 2010, about one-third of deaths in the United States occurred in short-stay general hospitals. Patients and doctors alike recognize that aggressive medical therapy may not be desired or even appropriate in the presence of advancing disease, and over time the use of hospice and palliative care facilities has increased. Most deaths in ICUs occur after an explicit decision to withdraw or withhold treatments.


Before the mid-20th century, the concept of beneficence in the eyes of physicians was strongly tied to preventing death. Ethical distinctions between acts of omission (“letting die”) and acts of commission (“killing”) were and remain confusing at best. Worse, physicians faced threats of criminal punishment if a patient’s death resulted from withdrawal of medical treatments. In 1976, the case of Karen Ann Quinlan established that patients have a right to forgo invasive treatments, even if lifesaving, and that surrogate decision makers could ask for withdrawal of lifesaving therapies if the surrogates could show that the patient would not have wanted them. The right to forgo lifesaving treatments was later extended in the cases of Claire Convoy and Nancy Cruzan to include any treatment if the patient refused it or if clear and convincing evidence indicated that the patient would have refused therapy if he or she could speak for himself or herself. These decisions were revisited and reconfirmed in the tragic case of Theresa Schiavo in 2005.


Arguments that withdrawing or withholding life-sustaining therapy does not violate rules against killing patients are based on ethical differences between killing and letting die, and between acts of commission (e.g., lethal injection) and acts of omission (e.g., withdrawal or withholding of ventilator therapy). Because such distinctions are confusing to both physicians and patients, a principle of proportionality is often applied when withholding or withdrawing treatments. In this principle, treatment is indicated to the extent that it is likely to present more benefits than burdens to the patient based on the patient’s perception of such medical, social, and psychological benefits and burdens. Of course, competent patients still always have the right to refuse therapy, even if lifesaving and otherwise indicated.


Two common settings in which anesthesiologists may be involved in withdrawing or withholding life-sustaining interventions are the ICU and the operating room before organ donation after cardiac death (DCD). In both cases, the issues and principles of withdrawing or withholding treatments are the same.


Withdrawal of life-sustaining interventions heralds the final phase of end-of-life care, and it is a socially critical phase in the life of the patient and family. Terminal care requires special knowledge and experience on the part of the physician. It requires expertise in medically supportive therapy, management of problematic symptoms, knowledge about physiologic changes in the dying patient, support and counseling of patients and families, understanding and respect for the patient’s autonomy and religious and cultural practices and beliefs, the ability to work within complex healthcare teams, the ability to communicate well, and empathy. Anyone intimately involved in care of the dying patient should also be intimately familiar with ethical and legal standards.


Withdrawal of life-sustaining treatment begins with an assessment of the individual patient’s physiology, level of dependence on therapy, degree of consciousness, preferences regarding sedation and analgesia, and preferences regarding privacy and level of involvement of family and other loved ones. All the patient’s treatment orders should be reviewed to meet the new treatment goals. Treatments promoting the patient’s comfort should generally be continued, whereas those directed only at physiologic maintenance may all be withdrawn. Family members and others attending the patient at the end of life should be educated about physical and mental changes they can expect to see as treatments are scaled back, including the possibility that death will not occur imminently once support is withdrawn.


Several interventions have ethical implications and deserve special consideration—fluid and nutritional management; the administration of sedatives and narcotics that have the potential to hasten death; the administration of neuromuscular blocking drugs; and deactivation of pacemakers, ventricular assist devices, and implantable cardioverter-defibrillators (ICDs).


The issue of fluid and nutritional support is controversial. Burdens associated with continuation of fluid and nutritional support include prolongation of the dying process, and complications and suffering from placement and maintenance of intravenous or enteral access (or both). However, feeding and hydration may have important connotations for family members and members of the healthcare team by allowing a sense of nurturing and mitigating feelings that they are “abandoning” the patient.


Pain, dyspnea, and depression are all common symptoms that cause suffering in the dying patient. Alleviating pain and dyspnea carry the risk of hastening death. Medical, legal, and religious authorities have all clearly accepted the principle of “double effect,” in which an action intended to produce a benefit for the patient produces not only the expected benefit but also the potential for significant harm. It is entirely ethical and legal to administer high doses of pain medication and sedatives for the intended effect of relieving suffering, even if the treatment has the side effect of hastening death. However, to administer any medication with the explicit intention of hastening death is euthanasia, and not medical therapy.


Terminal Sedation


“Terminal Sedation,” also known as “deep continuous sedation” (DCS), is an ethically controversial end-of-life strategy for patients who are suffering intolerable symptoms in the last stages of dying, and who do not respond well or completely to sedatives or pain medications that are being administered “as needed” in response to symptoms. In DCS, a decision is made with the patient or their appropriate surrogates to forgo reactive treatment of symptoms and to employ intravenous sedative/analgesic infusions with the intention of rendering the patient permanently unconscious until death occurs, but without the intention of causing death. While the goal of DCS—relief of suffering—is a laudable one, ethical questions nevertheless persist: the practice is plagued by vague and nonstandardized terminology and practice, a lack of outcomes research, an uncomfortable confusion with PAS and euthanasia, misunderstanding of the principle of double effect, and culturally diverse philosophies about the role of suffering and transcendence in the meaning of human life. Opponents suggest that DCS is merely euthanasia in disguise, invented to circumvent legal sanctions and moral objections. Some ethicists have argued that DCS permanently deprives the patient of morally relevant aspects of “personhood” and therefore represents a form of killing. Disturbing studies show that many physicians employing DCS actually do intend to hasten death.


A particularly controversial aspect of DCS is whether it can and should be allowed when the patient is suffering from severe and intractable existential suffering: fear, loneliness, anxiety, spiritual crises, and so forth. Professional guidelines regarding DCS and existential suffering at end of life differ greatly in their recommendations: the American Academy of Hospice and Palliative Medicine and the American College of Physicians do not make specific statements about DCS in existential suffering; the AMA Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs opposes DCS for existential suffering; the Royal Dutch Medical Association and the Harvard University Community Ethics Committee support the use of DCS in cases of existential suffering; and the Veterans Health Administration does not exclude it, but weighed against use of DCS for existential symptoms in their discussions. Even more questions arise when DCS is instituted in pediatric patients.


Neuromuscular Blocking Drugs


Neuromuscular blocking drugs have no anesthetic, analgesic, or sedative properties. Such drugs should not be initiated if withdrawal of ventilatory support is anticipated. Paralyzing the patient to comfort the family so that they see no disturbing movements or respirations as the patient dies is not justifiable. Even worse, it can mask symptoms and signs of distress and can thus prevent relief of suffering during the dying process. When withdrawal of ventilator support is anticipated in a patient already receiving such drugs, they should be withheld in all but extraordinary cases.


Implantable Cardiac Devices


When a patient who has a cardiac device requests withdrawal of life-sustaining interventions, questions can arise about whether it is ethical to deactivate or even explant such devices at the patient’s request. In the case of ICDs, the question might well be whether it is ethical to continue such therapy in a patient who has opted for palliative care. Recent studies provide concerning information: in the MADIT II trial, only 15% of patients who died had their ICD deactivated, after receiving “many” shocks at the last days of their lives. A post-mortem device interrogation study indicates that 31% of patients received shocks in the last 24 hours of life. It is likely that patients receiving shocks in the final hours of their lives may be unable to communicate that they are suffering this painful experience and ask to have it stopped. In another study, only 27% of patients had discussed deactivation of the ICD at end-of-life, raising concerns that failure to deactivate the device was due largely to failure of physician-to-patient communication that this was possible and should be considered. In some cases, physicians may lack the expertise or equipment to promptly deactivate such devices when inappropriate shocks are being delivered.


Some experts have said that that these devices must be treated differently from other medical interventions because by virtue of implantation they have become a “biofixture,” or literally a part of the patients themselves. Such arguments are difficult to sustain when we consider that many people undergo implantation of medical devices and subsequent explantation of them when the devices are no longer working or do not serve the patient’s purpose. Common examples include artificial joints, intraocular lenses, medication delivery devices, and orthopedic hardware. Furthermore, these devices are never uniquely a part of the patient in the same sense as DNA or their native organs. In fact, the ethical distinction between disabling a pacemaker in a pacer-dependent patient and turning off a ventilator for a ventilator-dependent patient is minimal if the request comes from a competent patient or the surrogate decision maker. Both actions involve discontinuance of artificial therapies that the patient no longer desires, and both may be followed by rapid death.


Consensus statements and guidelines by the Resuscitation Council of the UK, British Cardiovascular Society, and National Council for Palliative Care, the European Heart Rhythm Association, and Heart Rhythm Society, and the Canadian Cardiovascular Society all recommend discussion with the patient of deactivation of implantable cardiac devices in end-of-life care.


The presence of a do-not-resuscitate order should not be taken as an automatic request by the patient to discontinue implantable device therapy. As with other end-of-life therapies, discontinuance of such devices should include due consideration of whether the decision is made by a competent patient and with full informed consent. Management of discontinuance of device therapy should always include planning for treatment of distressing symptoms and administration of appropriate comfort measures.


Physician-Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia


PAS is defined as the provision of medication or prescriptions by a physician to a patient at their specific request for the explicit purpose of ending their life. PAS requires a patient who is both competent and capable of communicating the request, as well as capable of self-administration. Euthanasia is defined as the administration of medication by someone other than the patient for the express purpose of causing death in the belief that this would be best for the patient, but not necessarily at the specific request of the patient. Both practices differ ethically from withdrawing or withholding life-supporting medical treatments. In withdrawal or withholding of life-supporting treatment, the primary intention is to discontinue treatments that are causing suffering with an understanding that death may or probably will result. In PAS and euthanasia, the primary intention is to cause death, which secondarily ends suffering.


Currently, euthanasia is legal only in the Netherlands, Belgium, and Luxembourg. Some confusion exists about the status of euthanasia in Colombia, which has been labeled as allowing “euthanasia,” but appears in fact to have legalized PAS, reflecting a common misconception in the press about differences between the two practices. In the United States, euthanasia remains illegal regardless of circumstance, but PAS is legal as of 2018 in the states of Oregon, Washington, Montana, Vermont, Colorado, California, and the District of Columbia. It narrowly missed ratification in New Mexico after being passed by both state houses in 2017, and it passed the Hawaii State House of Representatives in March of 2018. It is also under consideration in other states. Thirty-seven states have specific laws that make PAS illegal, and four states have no specific laws regarding PAS. Internationally, PAS is legal only in the Netherlands, Belgium, Luxembourg, Germany, and Switzerland.


Supporters of PAS argue that the right to privacy and respect for autonomy support a patient’s right to determine the time, location, and circumstance of his or her own death. Patients consistently rate loss of autonomy and control, inability to pursue previously valued activities, and loss of dignity as the major concerns at the end of life. Adequate control of pain, anxiety, dyspnea, and other symptoms at the end of life remain a challenge to the medical profession, thereby fueling the desire for a means to end life when suffering cannot be controlled. Opponents argue that PAS “medicalizes” death, overly idealizes the physician-patient relationship, ignores possible personal and professional conflicts of interest, and leads to erosion of trust between dying patients and their doctors. Although many ethicists acknowledge that individual circumstances may make assisted suicide an ethically permissible action, most express concerns about potential abuse. Vulnerable members of society, such as the poor, old, and handicapped, could be pressed by financial and social factors into a suicide option in preference to palliative care. An additional argument against PAS or legalized euthanasia is that these approaches could provide solutions to the medical, social, and economic problems common to older and poor patients that are simpler and less expensive than seeking and requiring more difficult but definitive remedies.


Twenty years have passed since Oregon legalized and enacted PAS in 1997 and the Netherlands legalized both PAS and euthanasia, and significant data now provide some insights into whether these concerns about PAS and euthanasia are materializing. In recent polls, more than two thirds of the U.S. population polled favored legalizing PAS, and approximately 70% favored legalization of euthanasia. The percentage of U.S. oncology patients favoring a PAS or euthanasia option in end-of-life care is approximately 65%, whereas physicians frequently involved in end-of-life care, such as intensive care specialists, oncologists, and palliative care specialists, are the most uniformly opposed specialists. This finding represents a significant discordance between physicians and their patients.


In Oregon, where PAS has been legalized for the longest period in the United States, data from 2015 (the most recent year available) remain consistent and show that patients who requested PAS were more likely to be white and had generally higher economic status and education. More than 99.2% were insured, and 92.2% were enrolled in hospice care. Most were more than 65 years old (78%), and 72% were suffering from cancer. As of 2015, 36% of patients receiving prescriptions for PAS (a total of 1545 patients over 20 years) never used them and ultimately died of their underlying disease—with many surviving significantly longer than predicted. More than 92% of patients enrolled in the Oregon program cited loss of autonomy as a primary reason for pursuing the option. Some authors have suggested that the possession of a means to end their lives legally and humanely prevented “preemptive” suicides that could have occurred earlier and thus may have prolonged lives.


Concerns regarding abuses of PAS and euthanasia will undoubtedly continue, but thus far, evidence of systematic abuse is lacking in places where PAS is legalized and regulated. As the population ages and patients desire greater control over end-of-life care and circumstances, debate over PAS and euthanasia in the United States can be expected to continue to grow.


Ethical Issues in Organ Transplantation


Two issues critical to vital organ transplantation that confront anesthesiologists are the concept of brain death and the linkage of withdrawal of life-sustaining therapies with organ retrieval and transplantation after cardiac death (DCD).


Brain Death


Before the 1960s, death was defined as the moment when the heartbeat stopped and respirations ceased. Advances in cardiopulmonary resuscitation and mechanical ventilation then made it possible to postpone death, seemingly indefinitely. In 1968, the Ad Hoc Committee of the Harvard Medical School proposed redefining death as the point at which all cardiorespiratory function had irreversibly ceased, or all function of the whole brain had irreversibly stopped (brain death). The committee gave two explicit reasons for redefining death. The first was to allow patients to be declared dead and not maintained on machines—thus limiting expense; reallocating medical resources to other, salvageable patients; and allowing the social rituals surrounding death to occur. The second was to allow the donation of vital organs before circulation stopped.


Declaration of death further carries nonmedical consequences, such as the process of mourning, initiation of any criminal prosecutions, inheritance, taxation, and burial concerns. It was thus considered important that determinations of death follow consistent rules across state boundaries, and the National Conference on Uniform State Laws issued the Uniform Definition of Death Act in 1980, which was adopted by the states.


The public has been slow to accept brain death, in part because it requires complete trust in physicians and ignores indicators of death that the public already understands. To nonphysicians, brain-dead donors are superficially indistinguishable in many ways from living persons, and nonphysicians must therefore rely completely on the physician for both accurate and honest information of a loved one’s death. Recent court cases challenging declaration of death in patients who clearly did meet standard brain death criteria, such as that of Aden Hailu in Nevada, illustrate continued public uncertainty.


Medical standards in diagnosing brain death are relatively straightforward, although variations in the definition of death itself persist throughout the United States. In the United States, medical standards require demonstration that, in the absence of drugs, paralytic agents, hypothermia, and other reversible conditions that mimic loss of brain function, no cortical or brainstem function is present. The diagnosis is usually made either clinically, by demonstrating that cortical activity and brainstem reflexes are absent, or by radiographic studies demonstrating the complete absence of cerebral blood flow.


Although brain death is a social and not a biologic definition of death, medical, ethical, theological, and legal experts generally agree that brain death adequately defines a condition in which a person with ethical and legal rights and moral standing ceases to exist and should no longer be treated as though alive. Expensive medical interventions can be discontinued without legal ramifications, and vital organs can be donated for transplantation if the patient or the surrogate decision maker agrees.


Before assuming care of a brain-dead organ donor, the anesthesiologist is obligated to review the chart for documentation of the declaration of brain death and the criteria on which it was based. If any questions exist about the diagnosis, organ donation should be postponed until the anesthesiologist is satisfied that these concerns are addressed.


Donation after Cardiac Death


DCD occurs when a patient wishes to have life-sustaining medical therapies withdrawn and also wishes to proceed with vital organ donation after death. Controlling the time and place of death so that timing of organ donation can be optimized has obvious medical and ethical advantages. The decision to donate organs is made before death, thereby allowing time for discussion and informed consent. Organ ischemia time can be minimized. The dual decision to withdraw life-sustaining interventions and donate vital organs after death can create ethical conflicts, however. When a dying patient becomes an imminent organ donor, the risk is that the patient’s interests will be minimized or ignored in favor of the organ recipient.


The National Academy of Medicine reviewed DCD in 1997 and 2000 and found serious ethical questions, such as determining how quickly after asystole organ donation can begin and whether medications can ethically be administered to the donor before death that are solely for the purpose of organ preservation.


Ethical, theological, and legal principles prohibit us from killing one person to benefit another, but the point at which actual death has occurred in DCD donors is unclear. Although expedient donation is the very purpose of DCD, doctors must never sacrifice any living patient in the process or even take significant risks of doing so; the mistrust this would engender among the public could place the entire concept of DCD at risk by reducing potential donors and ultimately harming future potential organ recipients. Loss of consciousness occurs quickly after asystole, but brain function can continue for some time, and irreversible brain injury may not occur for many minutes. Yet some protocols call for organ retrieval to begin only 2 minutes after circulation has stopped, and in at least one institution, organ harvest is allowed to begin within seconds of cardiac arrest. Scientific and philosophic uncertainty exists about when death is complete—this could even lead to accusations that physicians deliberately kill patients to obtain organs for transplantation. Mistakes have occurred in some cases of brain-dead organ donors for which clear clinical criteria exist; DCD organ donation is potentially even more prone to error because no such clinical guidelines are universally accepted.


Donation of vital organs after brain death and DCD are both ethical and legal, but the interests of the dying patient must be absolutely protected until after death has occurred. Anesthesiologists can play a vital role in the organ donation process by helping hospitals develop reasonable and ethical policies for the management of brain-dead donors and DCD donors. Every anesthesiologist should be thoroughly familiar with brain death criteria and should review the process of brain death determination before accepting care of a brain-dead donor. It is inappropriate for anesthesiologists to be involved in organ DCD unless they have expertise in the relevant ethical, legal, and medical issues and are experienced in end-of-life care.

Only gold members can continue reading. Log In or Register to continue

Stay updated, free articles. Join our Telegram channel

Mar 7, 2020 | Posted by in ANESTHESIA | Comments Off on Ethical Aspects of Anesthesia Care

Full access? Get Clinical Tree

Get Clinical Tree app for offline access