Consent in laboring patients

html xmlns=”http://www.w3.org/1999/xhtml”>



7 Consent in laboring patients


Joanna M. Davies

Case 1






Sarah is a 32-year-old, gravida 1, para 0 in active labor at 4 cm cervical dilatation. She is experiencing considerable pain and requests an epidural for analgesia. However, as the anesthesiologist arrives, the patient’s husband, Tom, is telling the nurse that, prior to labor, his wife specifically told him that she did not want an epidural for pain, even if she begged for one, and he should not let her change her mind. This information is also written in her birth plan. Sarah is now screaming with each contraction and, despite receiving a total of 150 mcg of intravenous fentanyl, is adamant that she wants an epidural “now.”

Principle-based medical ethics focuses on the four concepts of autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence and justice. Over time, there has been movement from the beneficence driven paternalism of “doctor knows best” towards increasing patient autonomy. Authentic patient autonomy requires that the patients make their own decisions after they have received all of the relevant information pertinent to their situation and are therefore fully informed. Informed consent requires several elements: (1) capacity of the patient to make a decision, (2) freedom or voluntariness of the patient in decision-making, (3) disclosure of adequate information to the patient, (4) understanding of that information by the patient, and (5) consent by the patient to the procedure. Ensuring that these elements have been addressed and obtaining consent for procedures in laboring patients can be extremely challenging.

Can informed consent be obtained during the pain of labor?


There are conflicting views on whether informed consent is even possible during active labor. Black and Cyna, analyzed responses from 291 anesthesiologists surveyed about the risks they discussed with laboring patients, and whether it was possible to gain fully informed consent from them.1 Seventy percent considered active labor a barrier to the ability of a woman to give consent. However, a Society of Obstetric Anesthesia and Perinatology Anesthesiologists (SOAP) survey, published the same year (2006), found that 68% of 448 anesthesiologists thought that women in active labor are able to give informed consent.2 Scott has gone so far as to say “the only time when consent to an epidural to relieve the pain of labor is truly informed is in labor itself … when the person concerned knows what the pain is like.”3

Several studies of the patient’s perspective of informed consent during labor show that the pain of labor does not appear to interfere with the patient’s ability to hear and comprehend the information relevant to consent.4 Furthermore, a woman’s ability to understand epidural risks does not correlate with level of labor pain, anxiety, duration of pain, opioid medication, previous epidural experience or the desire for an epidural.5 In fact, the ability to recall the risks has been found to be similar in both laboring and nonlaboring, nonobstetric patients.6 Ideally, written or visual information about labor analgesia should be provided or at least available during prenatal visits to the obstetrician’s office in the antenatal period or during early labor allowing time for consideration of the available options and any questions.

Is Sarah’s consent impeded by the fentanyl she has received? In general the answer is poorly addressed in the literature. There are no US legal precedents regarding this issue and most institutions have inconsistent policies. Anesthesiologists can and do routinely make judgments about a patient’s capacity for informed consent based on the elements described above. There is normally no need to contact a psychiatrist or obtain legal advice. Sarah must have the mental capacity to comprehend and participate in the consent process and analgesia may allow her to do this. Withholding appropriate analgesia, particularly if there is a delay in the anesthesiologist obtaining consent, may in itself put the anesthesiologist in an unsupportable ethical position.

Ulysses directives


At this stage in her care, the literature supports that Sarah, despite being in severe pain and having received fentanyl, should be able to provide fully informed consent for epidural placement. However, an additional ethical dilemma has developed. Sarah’s husband, Tom, is insistent that Sarah does not really want an epidural and produces a written birthing plan which includes a statement that Sarah does not want to be permitted to deviate from this plan or her wishes concerning an epidural. Such a document is known as a “Ulysses directive” and brings into conflict the anesthesiologist’s beneficent desire to provide Sarah with analgesia, and the wish to respect Sarah’s autonomous decision to have a “natural” delivery.

However, autonomous decision-making brings with it the privilege for a woman to change her mind, especially if she has never experienced the pain of childbirth before. One might argue that Sarah’s directive be considered invalid because it was made at a time when the she was not fully informed. Antenatally, she may have been determined not to have an epidural. However, she may not have received appropriate information regarding the risks and benefits of epidurals, nor had she experienced labor pain previously. Information and valid experience are critical prerequisites for autonomous decision-making. While Scott considers it unethical “to withhold pain relief from a greatly distressed woman … solely because of a statement written in her birth plan..”, Thornton and Moore have argued that this “… does not respect her long-term preferences”, and hence her autonomy.”7 Other authors have even postulated that the duty of beneficence (in this case to relieve pain) may allow an intervention to proceed in the absence of informed consent until evidence of patient refusal is forthcoming.8 In this instance there is no unequivocal ethical ground upon which to stand and it has been suggested that the anesthesiologist be guided by the circumstances.9

Sarah is a primiparous woman at 4 cm cervical dilatation and is likely to be in labor for many more hours. Placing an epidural for analgesia is certainly an ethically defensible decision in this case. Interestingly, frequently it is the legal ramifications rather than the ethical debate that cause anesthesiologists the most concern. As a woman with capacity, Sarah can legally overrule her birth plan at any point. However, there is a risk after delivery, when the pain is long gone, that Sarah might feel she somehow “failed” during the birthing process by agreeing to have an epidural and see the anesthesiologist as an accomplice in this failure. This could result in an accusation of assault, or unconsented touching of the patient.

The anesthesiologist should be encouraged to see the patient and her family postpartum. At that time the anesthesiologist can discuss the events and reassure the patient that her decision was the correct one for the circumstances in which she found herself. It may help to inform the patient that relief of pain and stress during labor has benefits for the fetus and the course of labor. It is also wise to document the decision-making process that occurred. An example chart note might read:


After an appropriate consent process, the patient has decided to withdraw her previous refusal of epidural analgesia for labor. I will proceed based on her currently stated request for epidural analgesia.

In this particular case the ethical tension was resolved when the anesthesiologist conducted a patient and lengthy discussion with both Tom and Sarah. They agreed that they may not have appreciated how painful the labor would be, that an epidural would allow Sarah to enjoy the birth more, and that perhaps they had been naïve in her inexperience to completely refuse to consider all of her analgesic options.

How much information is enough?



How much information is too much and how long a discussion is too long during the throws of active labor? The amount of information given to Sarah regarding the risks and benefits of an epidural needs to be balanced against her level of pain and urgency to proceed. If possible, discussions should be held between contractions when the woman can focus on what she is being told. It is prudent to have this conversation with the patient’s support person present. Tom, in this case, will be able to ask questions and witness that the information has been provided. Every anesthesiologist has their own routine when providing information to a patient during the consent process. Brooks and Sullivan have aided the practitioner by developing a list of recommended issues that should be discussed with the patient.10 This list includes:
Jan 8, 2017 | Posted by in ANESTHESIA | Comments Off on Consent in laboring patients

Full access? Get Clinical Tree

Get Clinical Tree app for offline access